Moore's paradox of analysis strikes me as having a simpler resolution
than what recent commenters, such as Richard Fumerton in "The Paradox of Analysis," have proposed. The major premise of the paradox, as
Fumerton states it,
"If 'X is good' just means 'X is F' then
the question 'Is what is F good?' has the same meaning as the
question 'Is what is F, F?' " (478)
is unsound because it assumes that an object being "good" is
an identity statement (or at least, more charitably, that what is sought is an
identity statement). One arrives at the paradox by assuming that an analysis
just involves a chain of identities. In fact, what one wants here is an
equivalence, conditions such that if and only if they obtain, something is
good-- not an identity with the same intensional value under a different name. This latter
notion just perpetuates the basic error of the Meno.
For example, an informative analysis of "good" could ask how its extension is formed by treating it as a binary relation and asking what sub-properties it restricts its members to, as restrictions on the equivalence class of x := the set of things that are good. Taking good as a relation G, we might propose, for instance, that when x is mapped to the set u of things with a positive utility value by the relation G, the statement "x is good" is true.
A logical analysis along the lines of the above
without a necessary commitment to any one semantic interpretation could avoid
being either merely lexicographical or mysteriously phenomenological.
I'm not sure if it would be satisfying for all conceptual
analyses to be only the product of equivalences, but I would claim that
there is no satisfying conceptual analysis that is only the product of an
identity. Indeed, since this is already an intuition most people
have, Moore's reduction of conceptual analysis to an identity statement is
what makes the paradox of analysis work. The only problem is
that this reduction is wrong. In most cases, we do want an
equivalence statement with a conceptual analysis to tell us how and
when a concept obtains. (Maybe one could evoke Aristotle's four causes
here and say that an informative analysis should not just give us a noun phrase
that the concept noun stands in for but should give us one or more of these four
constitutive explanations.)
For example, if the concept is "triangle,"
there might be an identity relation with "three-sided polygon," but
this would not be informative-- it would just be a definition, a substitution
of a noun phrase for the concept noun, not an analysis-- while adding, that
"a triangle is any three-sided polygon such that it has three internal
angles that sum to 180 degrees" would be informative (e.g., by this
analytic definition we could claim that a three-sided polygon in non-Euclidean space
might not be a triangle). So, one could say that a conceptual analysis can
include identity definitions but cannot be constituted only by identity
definitions.
Also, because a satisfying conceptual analysis, such as the analysis of "triangle," can be constituted only from a combination of equivalence statements and identity statements, we can at least say that there are some paradigm cases of analysis that do not require some phenomenal state in addition to succeed.
No comments:
Post a Comment